Перевод: со всех языков на все языки

со всех языков на все языки

fitting+pin

  • 81 blade

    blade n
    лопатка
    airfoil-section blade
    профилированная лопатка
    air intake blade
    заглушка воздухозаборника
    airscrew blade incidence
    угол установки лопасти воздушного винта
    airscrew blade speed
    окружная скорость лопасти воздушного винта
    antitorque rotor blade
    лопасть рулевого винта
    articulated blade
    лопасть с шарнирной подвеской
    blade airfoil portion
    профильная часть лопатки
    blade angle
    угол установки лопасти
    blade attach fitting
    гребенка крепления лопасти
    blade attachment pin
    штифт крепления лопатки
    blade butt
    комель лопасти
    blade chord
    хорда лопасти
    blade counterweight
    противовес
    blade damper
    демпфер лопасти
    blade dome
    обтекатель комлевой части лопасти
    blade drag
    лобовое сопротивление лопатки
    blade droop
    зависание элеронов
    blade droop stop
    ограничитель свеса лопасти
    (несущего винта) blade flapping
    биение лопасти
    blade flyweight
    центробежный грузик лопасти
    blade foot
    комель лопасти
    blade leading edge
    передняя кромка лопасти
    blade metal cap
    предохранительная металлическая окантовка на передней кромке лопасти
    blade passage
    межлопаточный проход
    blade passing frequency
    частота вращения лопастей
    blade pitch scale
    шкала углов установки лопасти
    blade pressure side
    рабочая часть лопасти воздушного винта
    blade retainer
    стопор лопатки
    blade retaining plate
    пластинчатый замок крепления лопатки
    blade retention mechanism
    устройство для крепления лопасти
    blade ring
    лопаточный венец
    blade root
    хвостовик лопатки
    blade row
    лопаточный венец
    blade safety clip
    предохранительный зажим
    blade screwdriver
    перьевая отвертка
    blade section
    сечение лопасти
    blade slap
    срыв потока на лопасти
    blade slap phenomenon
    срыв потока на лопасти
    blade spacing
    шаг лопаток
    blades retaining ring
    стопорное кольцо лопаток
    blade stop cable
    стопорный трос
    blade stop gear
    фиксатор шага лопасти
    blades tracking
    установка соконусности лопастей
    blade tip
    законцовка лопасти
    blade tip light
    огонь конца лопасти
    blade titl
    наклон лопасти
    blade trim tab
    триммер лопасти
    blade wheel
    рабочее колесо
    detachable blade
    съемная лопатка
    dovetail blade attachment
    замок типа ласточкин хвост лопатки
    dovetailed blade
    лопатка, закрепленная замком типа ласточкиного хвоста
    file blade
    полотно напильника
    fir-tree blade attachment
    замок елочного типа лопатки
    fir-tree rooted blade
    лопатка, закрепленная замком елочного типа
    following blade vortex
    вихрь за лопастью
    groove-type blade attachment
    замок пазового типа лопатки двигателя
    hollow blade
    пустотелая лопатка
    keep clear of rotor blades
    остерегаться лопастей несущего винта
    leading blade vortex
    вихрь от предыдущей лопасти
    main rotor blade
    лопасть несущего винта
    move the blades to higher
    утяжелять воздушный винт
    moving blade
    поворотная лопатка
    outlet straightener blade
    лопатка спрямляющего аппарата
    pig-type blade attachment
    замок штифтового типа лопатки двигателя
    pinned blade
    лопатка, закрепленная штифтовым замком
    propeller blade
    лопасть воздушного винта
    propeller blade shank
    комель лопасти воздушного винта
    rotor blade
    лопатка ротора
    rotor blade spar
    лонжерон лопасти несущего винта
    stator blade
    лопатка статора
    straightener blade
    лопатка спрямляющего аппарата
    tail rotor blade
    лопасть рулевого винта
    turbine blade twist
    крутка лопатки турбины
    turbine rotor blade
    рабочая лопатка турбины
    variable blade
    регулируемая поворотная лопатка

    English-Russian aviation dictionary > blade

  • 82 Artificial Intelligence

       In my opinion, none of [these programs] does even remote justice to the complexity of human mental processes. Unlike men, "artificially intelligent" programs tend to be single minded, undistractable, and unemotional. (Neisser, 1967, p. 9)
       Future progress in [artificial intelligence] will depend on the development of both practical and theoretical knowledge.... As regards theoretical knowledge, some have sought a unified theory of artificial intelligence. My view is that artificial intelligence is (or soon will be) an engineering discipline since its primary goal is to build things. (Nilsson, 1971, pp. vii-viii)
       Most workers in AI [artificial intelligence] research and in related fields confess to a pronounced feeling of disappointment in what has been achieved in the last 25 years. Workers entered the field around 1950, and even around 1960, with high hopes that are very far from being realized in 1972. In no part of the field have the discoveries made so far produced the major impact that was then promised.... In the meantime, claims and predictions regarding the potential results of AI research had been publicized which went even farther than the expectations of the majority of workers in the field, whose embarrassments have been added to by the lamentable failure of such inflated predictions....
       When able and respected scientists write in letters to the present author that AI, the major goal of computing science, represents "another step in the general process of evolution"; that possibilities in the 1980s include an all-purpose intelligence on a human-scale knowledge base; that awe-inspiring possibilities suggest themselves based on machine intelligence exceeding human intelligence by the year 2000 [one has the right to be skeptical]. (Lighthill, 1972, p. 17)
       4) Just as Astronomy Succeeded Astrology, the Discovery of Intellectual Processes in Machines Should Lead to a Science, Eventually
       Just as astronomy succeeded astrology, following Kepler's discovery of planetary regularities, the discoveries of these many principles in empirical explorations on intellectual processes in machines should lead to a science, eventually. (Minsky & Papert, 1973, p. 11)
       Many problems arise in experiments on machine intelligence because things obvious to any person are not represented in any program. One can pull with a string, but one cannot push with one.... Simple facts like these caused serious problems when Charniak attempted to extend Bobrow's "Student" program to more realistic applications, and they have not been faced up to until now. (Minsky & Papert, 1973, p. 77)
       What do we mean by [a symbolic] "description"? We do not mean to suggest that our descriptions must be made of strings of ordinary language words (although they might be). The simplest kind of description is a structure in which some features of a situation are represented by single ("primitive") symbols, and relations between those features are represented by other symbols-or by other features of the way the description is put together. (Minsky & Papert, 1973, p. 11)
       [AI is] the use of computer programs and programming techniques to cast light on the principles of intelligence in general and human thought in particular. (Boden, 1977, p. 5)
       The word you look for and hardly ever see in the early AI literature is the word knowledge. They didn't believe you have to know anything, you could always rework it all.... In fact 1967 is the turning point in my mind when there was enough feeling that the old ideas of general principles had to go.... I came up with an argument for what I called the primacy of expertise, and at the time I called the other guys the generalists. (Moses, quoted in McCorduck, 1979, pp. 228-229)
       9) Artificial Intelligence Is Psychology in a Particularly Pure and Abstract Form
       The basic idea of cognitive science is that intelligent beings are semantic engines-in other words, automatic formal systems with interpretations under which they consistently make sense. We can now see why this includes psychology and artificial intelligence on a more or less equal footing: people and intelligent computers (if and when there are any) turn out to be merely different manifestations of the same underlying phenomenon. Moreover, with universal hardware, any semantic engine can in principle be formally imitated by a computer if only the right program can be found. And that will guarantee semantic imitation as well, since (given the appropriate formal behavior) the semantics is "taking care of itself" anyway. Thus we also see why, from this perspective, artificial intelligence can be regarded as psychology in a particularly pure and abstract form. The same fundamental structures are under investigation, but in AI, all the relevant parameters are under direct experimental control (in the programming), without any messy physiology or ethics to get in the way. (Haugeland, 1981b, p. 31)
       There are many different kinds of reasoning one might imagine:
        Formal reasoning involves the syntactic manipulation of data structures to deduce new ones following prespecified rules of inference. Mathematical logic is the archetypical formal representation. Procedural reasoning uses simulation to answer questions and solve problems. When we use a program to answer What is the sum of 3 and 4? it uses, or "runs," a procedural model of arithmetic. Reasoning by analogy seems to be a very natural mode of thought for humans but, so far, difficult to accomplish in AI programs. The idea is that when you ask the question Can robins fly? the system might reason that "robins are like sparrows, and I know that sparrows can fly, so robins probably can fly."
        Generalization and abstraction are also natural reasoning process for humans that are difficult to pin down well enough to implement in a program. If one knows that Robins have wings, that Sparrows have wings, and that Blue jays have wings, eventually one will believe that All birds have wings. This capability may be at the core of most human learning, but it has not yet become a useful technique in AI.... Meta- level reasoning is demonstrated by the way one answers the question What is Paul Newman's telephone number? You might reason that "if I knew Paul Newman's number, I would know that I knew it, because it is a notable fact." This involves using "knowledge about what you know," in particular, about the extent of your knowledge and about the importance of certain facts. Recent research in psychology and AI indicates that meta-level reasoning may play a central role in human cognitive processing. (Barr & Feigenbaum, 1981, pp. 146-147)
       Suffice it to say that programs already exist that can do things-or, at the very least, appear to be beginning to do things-which ill-informed critics have asserted a priori to be impossible. Examples include: perceiving in a holistic as opposed to an atomistic way; using language creatively; translating sensibly from one language to another by way of a language-neutral semantic representation; planning acts in a broad and sketchy fashion, the details being decided only in execution; distinguishing between different species of emotional reaction according to the psychological context of the subject. (Boden, 1981, p. 33)
       Can the synthesis of Man and Machine ever be stable, or will the purely organic component become such a hindrance that it has to be discarded? If this eventually happens-and I have... good reasons for thinking that it must-we have nothing to regret and certainly nothing to fear. (Clarke, 1984, p. 243)
       The thesis of GOFAI... is not that the processes underlying intelligence can be described symbolically... but that they are symbolic. (Haugeland, 1985, p. 113)
        14) Artificial Intelligence Provides a Useful Approach to Psychological and Psychiatric Theory Formation
       It is all very well formulating psychological and psychiatric theories verbally but, when using natural language (even technical jargon), it is difficult to recognise when a theory is complete; oversights are all too easily made, gaps too readily left. This is a point which is generally recognised to be true and it is for precisely this reason that the behavioural sciences attempt to follow the natural sciences in using "classical" mathematics as a more rigorous descriptive language. However, it is an unfortunate fact that, with a few notable exceptions, there has been a marked lack of success in this application. It is my belief that a different approach-a different mathematics-is needed, and that AI provides just this approach. (Hand, quoted in Hand, 1985, pp. 6-7)
       We might distinguish among four kinds of AI.
       Research of this kind involves building and programming computers to perform tasks which, to paraphrase Marvin Minsky, would require intelligence if they were done by us. Researchers in nonpsychological AI make no claims whatsoever about the psychological realism of their programs or the devices they build, that is, about whether or not computers perform tasks as humans do.
       Research here is guided by the view that the computer is a useful tool in the study of mind. In particular, we can write computer programs or build devices that simulate alleged psychological processes in humans and then test our predictions about how the alleged processes work. We can weave these programs and devices together with other programs and devices that simulate different alleged mental processes and thereby test the degree to which the AI system as a whole simulates human mentality. According to weak psychological AI, working with computer models is a way of refining and testing hypotheses about processes that are allegedly realized in human minds.
    ... According to this view, our minds are computers and therefore can be duplicated by other computers. Sherry Turkle writes that the "real ambition is of mythic proportions, making a general purpose intelligence, a mind." (Turkle, 1984, p. 240) The authors of a major text announce that "the ultimate goal of AI research is to build a person or, more humbly, an animal." (Charniak & McDermott, 1985, p. 7)
       Research in this field, like strong psychological AI, takes seriously the functionalist view that mentality can be realized in many different types of physical devices. Suprapsychological AI, however, accuses strong psychological AI of being chauvinisticof being only interested in human intelligence! Suprapsychological AI claims to be interested in all the conceivable ways intelligence can be realized. (Flanagan, 1991, pp. 241-242)
        16) Determination of Relevance of Rules in Particular Contexts
       Even if the [rules] were stored in a context-free form the computer still couldn't use them. To do that the computer requires rules enabling it to draw on just those [ rules] which are relevant in each particular context. Determination of relevance will have to be based on further facts and rules, but the question will again arise as to which facts and rules are relevant for making each particular determination. One could always invoke further facts and rules to answer this question, but of course these must be only the relevant ones. And so it goes. It seems that AI workers will never be able to get started here unless they can settle the problem of relevance beforehand by cataloguing types of context and listing just those facts which are relevant in each. (Dreyfus & Dreyfus, 1986, p. 80)
       Perhaps the single most important idea to artificial intelligence is that there is no fundamental difference between form and content, that meaning can be captured in a set of symbols such as a semantic net. (G. Johnson, 1986, p. 250)
        18) The Assumption That the Mind Is a Formal System
       Artificial intelligence is based on the assumption that the mind can be described as some kind of formal system manipulating symbols that stand for things in the world. Thus it doesn't matter what the brain is made of, or what it uses for tokens in the great game of thinking. Using an equivalent set of tokens and rules, we can do thinking with a digital computer, just as we can play chess using cups, salt and pepper shakers, knives, forks, and spoons. Using the right software, one system (the mind) can be mapped into the other (the computer). (G. Johnson, 1986, p. 250)
        19) A Statement of the Primary and Secondary Purposes of Artificial Intelligence
       The primary goal of Artificial Intelligence is to make machines smarter.
       The secondary goals of Artificial Intelligence are to understand what intelligence is (the Nobel laureate purpose) and to make machines more useful (the entrepreneurial purpose). (Winston, 1987, p. 1)
       The theoretical ideas of older branches of engineering are captured in the language of mathematics. We contend that mathematical logic provides the basis for theory in AI. Although many computer scientists already count logic as fundamental to computer science in general, we put forward an even stronger form of the logic-is-important argument....
       AI deals mainly with the problem of representing and using declarative (as opposed to procedural) knowledge. Declarative knowledge is the kind that is expressed as sentences, and AI needs a language in which to state these sentences. Because the languages in which this knowledge usually is originally captured (natural languages such as English) are not suitable for computer representations, some other language with the appropriate properties must be used. It turns out, we think, that the appropriate properties include at least those that have been uppermost in the minds of logicians in their development of logical languages such as the predicate calculus. Thus, we think that any language for expressing knowledge in AI systems must be at least as expressive as the first-order predicate calculus. (Genesereth & Nilsson, 1987, p. viii)
        21) Perceptual Structures Can Be Represented as Lists of Elementary Propositions
       In artificial intelligence studies, perceptual structures are represented as assemblages of description lists, the elementary components of which are propositions asserting that certain relations hold among elements. (Chase & Simon, 1988, p. 490)
       Artificial intelligence (AI) is sometimes defined as the study of how to build and/or program computers to enable them to do the sorts of things that minds can do. Some of these things are commonly regarded as requiring intelligence: offering a medical diagnosis and/or prescription, giving legal or scientific advice, proving theorems in logic or mathematics. Others are not, because they can be done by all normal adults irrespective of educational background (and sometimes by non-human animals too), and typically involve no conscious control: seeing things in sunlight and shadows, finding a path through cluttered terrain, fitting pegs into holes, speaking one's own native tongue, and using one's common sense. Because it covers AI research dealing with both these classes of mental capacity, this definition is preferable to one describing AI as making computers do "things that would require intelligence if done by people." However, it presupposes that computers could do what minds can do, that they might really diagnose, advise, infer, and understand. One could avoid this problematic assumption (and also side-step questions about whether computers do things in the same way as we do) by defining AI instead as "the development of computers whose observable performance has features which in humans we would attribute to mental processes." This bland characterization would be acceptable to some AI workers, especially amongst those focusing on the production of technological tools for commercial purposes. But many others would favour a more controversial definition, seeing AI as the science of intelligence in general-or, more accurately, as the intellectual core of cognitive science. As such, its goal is to provide a systematic theory that can explain (and perhaps enable us to replicate) both the general categories of intentionality and the diverse psychological capacities grounded in them. (Boden, 1990b, pp. 1-2)
       Because the ability to store data somewhat corresponds to what we call memory in human beings, and because the ability to follow logical procedures somewhat corresponds to what we call reasoning in human beings, many members of the cult have concluded that what computers do somewhat corresponds to what we call thinking. It is no great difficulty to persuade the general public of that conclusion since computers process data very fast in small spaces well below the level of visibility; they do not look like other machines when they are at work. They seem to be running along as smoothly and silently as the brain does when it remembers and reasons and thinks. On the other hand, those who design and build computers know exactly how the machines are working down in the hidden depths of their semiconductors. Computers can be taken apart, scrutinized, and put back together. Their activities can be tracked, analyzed, measured, and thus clearly understood-which is far from possible with the brain. This gives rise to the tempting assumption on the part of the builders and designers that computers can tell us something about brains, indeed, that the computer can serve as a model of the mind, which then comes to be seen as some manner of information processing machine, and possibly not as good at the job as the machine. (Roszak, 1994, pp. xiv-xv)
       The inner workings of the human mind are far more intricate than the most complicated systems of modern technology. Researchers in the field of artificial intelligence have been attempting to develop programs that will enable computers to display intelligent behavior. Although this field has been an active one for more than thirty-five years and has had many notable successes, AI researchers still do not know how to create a program that matches human intelligence. No existing program can recall facts, solve problems, reason, learn, and process language with human facility. This lack of success has occurred not because computers are inferior to human brains but rather because we do not yet know in sufficient detail how intelligence is organized in the brain. (Anderson, 1995, p. 2)

    Historical dictionary of quotations in cognitive science > Artificial Intelligence

  • 83 sleeve

    1. штуцер
    2. цилиндрический контакт
    3. переходная коническая втулка
    4. нарукавник
    5. корпус (муфты)
    6. коаксиальный экран
    7. гнездовая контакт-деталь
    8. гильза (цилиндра насоса) (втулка)
    9. гильза
    10. втулка катушки индуктивности
    11. бандаж (металлургия)

     

    бандаж
    1. Спец. сорт. прокат для изгот. наруж. опорной части состав, ж.-д. колеса. Б. цельнокат. черн. для подвижн. состава (локомотивов, трамваев, вагонов) изгот. на бандажных прокатных станах из предварит. осаж. слитков или круглой НЛЗ из углерод. сталей. Произв. б. с гребнем и без гребня наруж. диам. до 2 м и толщ. до 160 мм. Поставл. в термообработ. сост.
    2. Стальной пояс, надев. на кожух печи для увелич. ее прочн.
    3. Наруж. раб. часть состав. листопрокатного валка, изгот. ковкой или порош. металлургией.
    [ http://metaltrade.ru/abc/a.htm]

    Тематики

    EN

     

    втулка катушки индуктивности
    втулка

    Ндп. букса
    Деталь конструкции из диэлектрического материала, имеющая форму полого гладкого или резьбового цилиндра, предназначенная для перемещения подстроечника.
    Примечание
    Втулка может использоваться для крепления катушки в блоках аппаратуры.
    [ ГОСТ 20718-75

    Недопустимые, нерекомендуемые

    Тематики

    Синонимы

    EN

    FR

     

    гильза
    Вспомогательное упаковочное средство, имеющее форму трубки для наматывания бумаги или гибких материалов.
    [ ГОСТ 17527-2003]

    Тематики

    • упаковка, упаковывание

    Обобщающие термины

    EN

    DE

    FR

     

    гильза (цилиндра насоса) (втулка)
    стакан (втулка)
    трубка (втулка)
    полный вал (втулка)


    [ http://slovarionline.ru/anglo_russkiy_slovar_neftegazovoy_promyishlennosti/]

    Тематики

    Синонимы

    EN

     

    гнездовая контакт-деталь
    Контакт-деталь, предназначенная для ввода штыревой контакт-детали и электрического контактирования с ней по своей внутренней поверхности
    [ ГОСТ 14312-79]

    гнездовой контакт
    -

    [IEV number 151-12-17]

    EN

    socket contact
    female contact
    contact member intended to make electric engagement on its inner surface for mating with the outer surface of another contact member
    NOTE – In English, the term "socket contact" does not imply that socket contacts are always mounted in a socket nor that sockets have only socket contacts.
    Source: 581-02-07 MOD, 151-12-20
    [IEV number 151-12-17]

    FR

    contact femelle, m
    élément de contact destiné à établir la liaison électrique sur ses faces intérieures en s'accouplant avec les faces extérieures d'un autre élément de contact
    NOTE – L’emploi en anglais du terme "socket contact" n’implique pas qu’un contact femelle est toujours monté dans un socle, ni que les socles ne comportent que des contacts femelles.
    Source: 581-02-07 MOD, 151-12-20
    [IEV number 151-12-17]

    0222_1
    Рис. Tyco Electronics

    1 - Гнездовая контакт-деталь (гнездовой контакт)
    2 - Штыревая контакт-деталь (штыревой контакт)

    Параллельные тексты EN-RU

     

    Under the CEE/IEC system, pins and sleeves must be differently spaced in devices with different numbers of poles, and the earthing pin and earthing sleeve are larger than the other pins and sleeves.
    [ABB]

    В соответствии с требованиями CEE/МЭК расположение штыревых и гнездовых контактов в соединителях с разным числом полюсов не должно быть одинаковым. Кроме того, размеры заземляющего штыря и гнезда должны быть больше размеров остальных штырей и гнезд.
    [Перевод Интент]

    Недопустимые, нерекомендуемые

    Тематики

    Обобщающие термины

    Синонимы

    EN

    DE

    FR

     

    коаксиальный экран

    [Я.Н.Лугинский, М.С.Фези-Жилинская, Ю.С.Кабиров. Англо-русский словарь по электротехнике и электроэнергетике, Москва, 1999 г.]

    Тематики

    • электротехника, основные понятия

    EN

     

    переходная коническая втулка
    переходный конус


    [ http://slovarionline.ru/anglo_russkiy_slovar_neftegazovoy_promyishlennosti/]

    Тематики

    Синонимы

    EN

     

    цилиндрический контакт

    [Я.Н.Лугинский, М.С.Фези-Жилинская, Ю.С.Кабиров. Англо-русский словарь по электротехнике и электроэнергетике, Москва, 1999 г.]

    Тематики

    • электротехника, основные понятия

    EN

     

    штуцер
    Элемент, предназначенный для присоединения к сосуду трубопроводов, трубопроводной арматуры, контрольно-измерительных приборов и т.п.
    [ПБ 03-576-03]

    штуцер
    Деталь, предназначенная для присоединения к трубопроводу арматуры, контрольно-измерительных приборов и т.п.
    [ПБ 03-108-96]

    штуцер
    Деталь, используемая для того, чтобы соединять два трубопровода по длине или для того, чтобы присоединять к шлангу другое оборудование.
    [РД 01.120.00-КТН-228-06]

    Тематики

    EN

    Англо-русский словарь нормативно-технической терминологии > sleeve

  • 84 נגר

    נָגָרm. (preced. wds.) ( trimmed chip, door-bolt, pin fitting into sockets top and bottom. Erub.X, 10, v. גְּלֹוסְטְרָא. Ib. 11, v. גָּרַר. B. Bath. 101a (in Chald. dict.) דעביד להו כמין נ׳ he made the sepulchral chambers like an upright bolt, i. e. placed the bodies in an upright position. Men.33a עשאה כמין נ׳ if he fastened the door-post inscription ( מזוזה) so as to look like a bolt shoved into a case, i. e. horizontally. Y.Meg.IV, end, 75c בית מזוזתו … כמין נ׳ the case for the inscription in Rabbis house was made like an upright bolt (reaching the top of the door). Num. R. s. 15; Yalk. Josh. 32 יריחי היתה נְגָרָהּוכ׳ (not נגרא) Jericho was the bolt of Palestine; a. fr.

    Jewish literature > נגר

  • 85 נָגָר

    נָגָרm. (preced. wds.) ( trimmed chip, door-bolt, pin fitting into sockets top and bottom. Erub.X, 10, v. גְּלֹוסְטְרָא. Ib. 11, v. גָּרַר. B. Bath. 101a (in Chald. dict.) דעביד להו כמין נ׳ he made the sepulchral chambers like an upright bolt, i. e. placed the bodies in an upright position. Men.33a עשאה כמין נ׳ if he fastened the door-post inscription ( מזוזה) so as to look like a bolt shoved into a case, i. e. horizontally. Y.Meg.IV, end, 75c בית מזוזתו … כמין נ׳ the case for the inscription in Rabbis house was made like an upright bolt (reaching the top of the door). Num. R. s. 15; Yalk. Josh. 32 יריחי היתה נְגָרָהּוכ׳ (not נגרא) Jericho was the bolt of Palestine; a. fr.

    Jewish literature > נָגָר

См. также в других словарях:

  • pin fastener — ▪ machine component       a steel pin, usually cylindrical, that can keep machine parts in proper alignment or fasten them together. The illustration shows several types of pin fasteners in common use.       Hardened and precisely shaped dowel… …   Universalium

  • pin (fastener) — In mechanical and civil engineering, a peg or bar designed to fasten machine and structural components together or to keep them aligned. Dowel pins are used to keep machine components aligned, sometimes without making a rigid joint (as in a pin… …   Universalium

  • Split (ten pin bowling) — A split is a term in ten pin bowling used to describe a number of situations where two or more pins remain standing after the first ball of a frame with a gap between them, when the headpin (the number 1 pin ) is no longer standing after the… …   Wikipedia

  • Compression seal fitting — A Compression seal fitting, also known as a sealing gland, is intended to seal some type of element (probe, wire, conductor, pipe, tube, fiber optic cable) when the element must pass through a pressure or environmental boundary. A compression… …   Wikipedia

  • toggle pin — noun : a pin with a shoulder and eye at one end and at the other a hinged locking device that prevents the pin from being withdrawn from a fitting until the locking device is in line with the pin …   Useful english dictionary

  • Dowel pin — Dowel Dow el, n. [Cf. G. d[ o]bel peg, F. douelle state of a cask, surface of an arch, douille socket, little pipe, cartridge.] (Mech.) 1. A pin, or block, of wood or metal, fitting into holes in the abutting portions of two pieces, and being… …   The Collaborative International Dictionary of English

  • Vuelo 1862 de El Al — Lugar del choque del avión en Bijlmer. Fecha 4 de octubre de 1992 Causa …   Wikipedia Español

  • Steam locomotive — A steam locomotive is a locomotive powered by steam. The term usually refers to its use on railways, but can also refer to a road locomotive such as a traction engine or steamroller.Steam locomotives dominated rail traction from the mid 19th… …   Wikipedia

  • BS 1363 — British Standard BS 1363 specifies the type of domestic AC power plugs and sockets most commonly used in the United Kingdom, Cyprus, Ireland, Malta, Malaysia, Singapore and many former British colonies. Of these, Ireland, Malaysia and Singapore… …   Wikipedia

  • AC power plugs and sockets — See also: Industrial and multiphase power plugs and sockets Plugs and sockets may sometimes combine male and female contacts, but t …   Wikipedia

  • Schrader valve — The Schrader valve, invented by August Schrader in the 1890s, consists of a valve stem into which a valve core is threaded, and is used on virtually all automobile tires and wider rimmed bicycle tires. The valve core is a poppet valve assisted by …   Wikipedia

Поделиться ссылкой на выделенное

Прямая ссылка:
Нажмите правой клавишей мыши и выберите «Копировать ссылку»